RE: Ideological blinders *and* enablers

From: Damien Broderick (damienb@unimelb.edu.au)
Date: Mon Mar 31 2003 - 22:46:47 MST

  • Next message: hubert mania: "Re: META: Greg Burch's request"

    At 07:05 PM 3/31/03 -0800, Lee Corbin wrote:

    >Hal Finney writes

    >> It's mundane, but we can start with the definition
    >> of "ideology" from dictionary.com:
    >
    >> 1. The body of ideas reflecting the social needs and aspirations of an
    >> individual, group, class, or culture.
    >> 2. A set of doctrines or beliefs that form the basis of a political,
    >> economic, or other system.
    >
    >> In the crudest form, ideological blinders prevent someone from seeing and
    >> thinking about facts which would contradict the ideology.

    >The most important aspect to me is whether we can distinguish
    >political ideologies---in their effects---from other systems
    >of belief. For example, most of your analysis might equally
    >well apply, it seems to me, to my convictions about
    >certain scientific or historical matters.

    One problem here is in discerning the limits of `political' as a framing
    adjective. Feminist critique, for all its excesses, has shown convincingly
    the ideological forces skewing, constraining, even largely *creating* the
    ways most men and women in the Western 1950s, say, understood what it is to
    be a male or a female human. This construction was largely invisible to
    those involved; it was *just how the world is*. If you were a black man or
    woman, you had further layers of ideological shaping simultaneously imposed
    *on* you and internalized *inside* you. That's ideology: not what political
    opinions you happen to find fashionable, but the immense social
    constraining and enabling powers of discourse.

    Of what?

    Oh well, here's a bit from THE ARCHITECTURE OF BABEL. I probably posted
    this last time around, but it might provide some chewy nuggets:

    ============

    A discourse, in general terms, is a kind of local communication field which
    arises in the unexplored linguistic gap between the realms of langue and
    parole. Discourse, that is, has some of the characteristics of a language
    system, as a competence at a high level of abstraction, which yet arises
    out of the performative speech acts which mediate the day-to-day exercise
    of power and knowledge. Perhaps each discourse, in as much as it can be
    specified, is a slice through the polysemous jangle-jungle of conflicting
    meanings which become attached (through conflicts, and the pressure of
    novelties of every kind) to each human utterance or inscription.

    Let us look briefly at some of the typical moves in that variety of
    discourse theory which is an offshoot of Althusserian Marxism, as discussed
    in a survey by Diane Macdonell (1986).

    Typically enough, Macdonell's attempted redemption of Althusser ascribes
    the relativist, constructivist commonplaces of discourse theory to what she
    calls his `radical breakthrough' (p. 13). Suddenly, after the 1969 essay
    `Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses', intellectuals in the French
    Communist Party were urged to see that superstructural social phenomena
    like families, religions and education (now `ISAs') might be as causally
    significant as brute `relations of economic production'. Is it unfair of me
    to belittle Althusser's discovery as a commonplace? Has not theory, under
    his influence, opened our understanding of the self to unprecedented voids
    of uncertainty? Not altogether unprecedented. Consider that much-debunked
    falsificationist Karl Popper, on the topic of subjectivity:

          "It seems to me of considerable importance that we are not born as
    selves, but that we have to learn that we are selves; in fact we have to
    learn to be selves....

          "I suggest that a consciousness of self begins to develop through the
    medium of other persons: just as we learn to see ourselves in a mirror, so
    the child becomes conscious of himself by sensing his reflection in the
    mirror of other people's consciousness of himself." (Popper and Eccles,
    1977, pp. 109-10)

    Popper's figure of the mirror is not a sly appropriation of one of theory's
    favorite tropes. As he points out, it goes back at least to Adam Smith
    (1759: The Theory of Moral Sentiments) who `puts forward the idea that
    society is a "mirror" which enables the individual to see and to "think of
    his own character, of the propriety or demerit of his own sentiments and
    conduct, of the beauty or deformity of his own mind", which suggests that
    if it were "possible that a human creature could grow up to manhood in some
    solitary place, without any communication with his own species" then he
    could not develop a self' (cited in Popper and Eccles, p. 111).

    While not precisely gleaming with dark Lacanian opacity, this bourgeois
    classic is not very far from the celebrated entry via Alice's Looking Glass
    to the Symbolic Order, and Althusser's construction of subjecthood via the
    process of `hailing' or `interpellation' by another.

    The difference, of course, lies in the sustained Althusserian attack on any
    `human nature' which might be considered necessary to underpin the
    effectiveness of any process of interpellation. As Terry Eagleton says, it
    is ineffective to baptize a badger (Eagleton, 1983, p. 118; he is
    discussing Austin and illocutionary acts). In much the same way, it is also
    ineffective to interpellate a chair, or even a computer (although often
    enough I find myself doing so). Althusser, of course, was aware of this
    flaw in his case and attempted to correct it by what seems to me
    self-evidently a vacuous re-definition:

          "[I]deology hails or interpellates individuals as subjects. As
    ideology is eternal, I must now suppress the temporal form in which I have
    presented the functioning of ideology, and say: ideology has always-already
    interpellated individuals as subjects, which amounts to making it clear
    that individuals are always-already interpellated by ideology as subjects,
    which necessarily leads us to one last proposition: individuals are
    always-already subjects." (Althusser, 1984, pp. 49-50)

    The sole sense which can be made of this - Althusser says it `might seem
    paradoxical' (p. 50), and he is right - is that individuals are genetically
    predisposed to take the imprint of culture. We are `primed' to be
    interpellated. Now as it happens (it could have been otherwise; we might
    have been social insects) the kind of pre-formation this is lends itself to
    the experience of inner consciousness, self-motivation, whether this be
    valorized as `individual initiative' or stigmatized as `original sin',
    `bourgeois illusion', or the clamor of Maya.

    ...the books mentioned, now all rather old:

    Althusser, Louis (1984) Essays on Ideology, London: Verso

    Eagleton, Terry (1983) Literary Theory: An Introduction, Oxford: Blackwell

    [and see also Eagleton, Terry (1991) Ideology: An Introduction, London: Verso]

    Macdonell, Diane (1986) Theories of Discourse: An Introduction, Oxford:
    Blackwell

    Popper, Karl and John Eccles (1977) The Self and its Brain: An Argument for
    Interactionism, Berlin: Springer International

    ================

    That's obviously not intended as a substantive reply to either Hal or Lee,
    but as a hint of where one might need to look for further elaborated
    discussions.

    Damien Broderick



    This archive was generated by hypermail 2.1.5 : Mon Mar 31 2003 - 22:50:44 MST