Kant's enlightenment

From: Damien Broderick (damienb@unimelb.edu.au)
Date: Tue Aug 19 2003 - 07:38:48 MDT

  • Next message: Robbie Lindauer: "Re: mutating into neoconservative thinktanks?"

    I just did a free rendering into somewhat idiomatic English of the great
    philosopher Kant's key essay (for a German newspaper) on the topic of the
    Enlightenment. Of course, where I speak of representatives and elected
    heads of state he was speaking of Frederick the all powerful ruler; he
    meant Prussia where we tend to read the USA. His tone is somewhat
    chillingly patronizing to most of his fellow citizens, but that isn't alien
    to many posts on this list. What is disturbing is how little the rhetoric
    and argument has changed in nearly a quarter of a millennium.

    The most hilarious line comes toward the end, where Kant mentions that at
    least these pesky thought controllers don't try to interfere with our
    choices in science and the arts. Maybe this was bleak irony, but I suspect
    it was just that few people had access to either, and that the sciences had
    not yet revealed their power.

    When I say `idiomatic' I'm speaking loosely; the tone that comes through
    still has a musty 1930s flavor. You can compare a more literal
    interpretation at

    http://eserver.org/philosophy/kant/what-is-enlightenment.txt

    Damien Broderick

    =======================

    IMMANUEL KANT
    An Answer to the Question: "What is Enlightenment?"
    Konigsberg in Prussia, 30th September, 1784.

    Enlightenment is our emergence from self-imposed intellectual submission.
    By submission I mean the refusal to trust your own grasp of reality, bowing
    to the dictates of authority. What's lacking in the submissive isn't any
    raw capacity for understanding, but the resolution and courage to use it
    without kowtowing to imposed direction. So the motto of enlightenment is:
    Have the guts to use your own intelligence, to follow your own reasoning!
            Why do so many people happily submit their whole lives long to authority?
    Laziness and cowardice! This allows a few among us, all too easily, to set
    themselves up as guardians over the rest. It's so convenient to drift
    along! If I can depend on a manual of instructions, a spiritual adviser to
    serve as my conscience, a doctor to choose my prescriptions, all the rest
    of it, I needn't make any effort. Don't think, just pay up and toe the
    line; let others take over the tedious job of thinking for me.
            Those do-gooders who generously accepted the task of running our lives
    quickly made sure that the majority think any step in the direction of
    self-command must be extremely dangerous and difficult. First they dumb us
    down, then they lead us by the nose. In reality, the danger isn't so very
    great. Despite a few early topples, everyone eventually learns to walk. But
    falling on your face intellectually is intimidating, and usually frightens
    us off from further attempts.
            Such self-imposed submission becomes almost second nature, so for an
    isolated individual it's hard to work your way free. You grow fond of being
    told what to do and think-it's nice to have someone else do the work for
    you! When you've never been allowed to make the attempt, you lose the
    capacity to exercise your own understanding. Dogmas and formulas come to
    seem the automatic and rational default. In fact, they're a brake. Yet if
    you wiggle free of those rules you find you're paralyzed, since you're
    unaccustomed to moving by yourself. To date, only a few individuals have
    cultivated their own minds sufficiently to free themselves from management
    by others.
            By contrast, an entire community stands a better chance of enlightening
    itself. In fact, if people are left free to work things out for themselves
    in a spirit of solidarity, enlightenment is almost inevitable. Here's how
    it works: even among the elite, there'll always be those few who do think
    for themselves. Once they make the breakthrough to enlightenment, they can
    start to spread the spirit of rational respect for personal value, for the
    duty we all have to think for ourselves. Strangely, though, a public that's
    been under the thumb of self-appointed guardians is likely to insist on
    retaining the status quo. Numbing routines of thought finally avenge
    themselves on the very people who first established the rules (or whose
    predecessors did so). A community can only achieve enlightenment slowly,
    working against this inertia.
            A bloody revolution may well succeed in putting an end to autocratic
    despotism, to rapacious or power-seeking oppression-but it can never
    produce a true reform in ways of thinking. Instead, new knee-jerk habits,
    no better than the ones they replaced, will emerge to control the
    thoughtless majority.
            For enlightenment, all that's needed is freedom of public speech, the most
    innocuous form of all: freedom to make public use of your reason, whatever
    the issue. Yet around the world we hear: Don't argue! The military roar:
    Don't argue, get in line! The tax-official: Don't argue, pay up! The
    clergyman, the rabbi, the mullah: Don't argue, trust in God! By contrast,
    our own enlightenment culture says: Argue as much as you like and about
    whatever you like, with one proviso: At the end of the arguments, obey the
    law!
            So there are restrictions on freedom everywhere. Yet while some
    restrictions prevent enlightenment, others actually promote it. Here's the
    paradox: the public use of reason must always be free, and by itself it can
    bring about enlightenment. But private reasoning may quite often be very
    narrowly restricted, without unduly hindering the progress of
    enlightenment. The public use of your own reason is what we might call the
    work of the public intellectual, addressing the community in informed
    debate. What I've termed the private use of reason is the mental activity
    required when you accept a task with which you're entrusted.
            For example, it would be damaging if a military officer on duty quibbled
    openly about the appropriateness or usefulness of an order. He must simply
    obey his superior. But he can't reasonably be stopped from commenting on
    any errors in the military service, even putting these criticisms forward
    publicly for judgement. A citizen can't refuse to pay taxes levied on him,
    but he doesn't contravene his civil obligations by publicly voicing
    objections to the impropriety or even injustice of such taxes. A clergyman
    is employed by a church on condition that he will instruct pupils and
    congregation in accordance with its doctrines. But as a scholar, he is not
    only completely free but also obliged to covey to the community his
    carefully considered, well-intentioned thoughts on any mistaken aspects of
    those doctrines, and to offer suggestions for a better arrangement of
    religious and ecclesiastical affairs.
            And there is nothing in this division of rights and responsibilities to
    trouble the conscience. He'll say: Our church teaches the following
    doctrine, using the following arguments. He then extracts as much practical
    value as possible for his congregation even from precepts he harbors some
    doubts about, but which he can nevertheless undertake to expound, since it
    is not in fact wholly impossible that they may contain truth. Of course if
    the clergyman found anything opposed to the essence of religion in them,
    he'd have to resign his post rather than teach against his conscience.
    Conversely, as a scholar addressing the world at large through his
    writings, the clergyman making public use of his reason enjoys unlimited
    freedom to use his own reason and to speak in his own person. Otherwise
    there is no means to break free of error, an absurdity which amounts to
    making absurdities permanent.
            A social contract intended to prevent all further enlightenment of
    humankind forever is absolutely null and void, however solemnly ratified.
    One age cannot enter into an alliance on oath to put the next age in a
    position where it would be impossible for it to extend and correct its
    knowledge, particularly on such important matters, or to make any progress
    whatsoever in enlightenment. This would be a crime against human nature,
    whose original destiny lies precisely in such progress. Later generations
    are thus perfectly entitled to dismiss these agreements as unauthorized and
    criminal. To test whether any particular measure can be agreed upon as a
    law for a people, we need only ask whether a people could justifiably
    impose such a law upon itself. This might well be possible for a specified
    short period as a means of introducing a certain order, pending, as it
    were, a better solution. This would also mean that each citizen,
    particularly the ethicist, would be given a free hand as a scholar to
    comment publicly, that is, in writings, on the inadequacies of current
    institutions. Meanwhile, the newly established order would continue to
    exist, until public insight into the nature of such matters had progressed
    and proved itself to the point where, by general (if not unanimous) consent
    a proposal could be submitted to the lawmakers.
            But it is absolutely impermissible to agree, even for a single lifetime,
    to a permanent ethical constitution which no-one might publicly question.
    For this would virtually nullify a phase in humanity's upward progress,
    thus making it fruitless and even detrimental to subsequent generations.
    For a limited period, you may ethically postpone enlightening yourself in
    matters you ought to know about. But to renounce such enlightenment
    completely, whether for yourself or even more so for later generations,
    means violating and trampling underfoot the sacred rights of humankind.
            But if people may not even impose such a restriction upon itself, still
    less can it legitimately be imposed upon it by their leaders. Their
    legislative authority depends precisely upon their role in uniting the
    collective will of the people. So long as they see to it that all proposed
    improvements are compatible with civil order, leaders can otherwise leave
    the citizenry to do whatever we find necessary for our betterment, which is
    our own business. The role of law-makers and enforcers is to stop anyone
    forcibly hindering others from working as best they can to define and
    promote their well-being
            Do we yet live in an enlightened age? No, but we do live in an age of
    enlightenment. As things stand at present, we still have a long way to go
    before people generally are in a position (or can ever be put into a
    position) of using their own understanding confidently and well in ethical
    matters, without outside guidance. But there are distinct indications that
    the way is now being cleared for the populace to work freely in this
    direction, and that the obstacles to universal enlightenment, to our
    emergence from his self-imposed submission, are gradually becoming fewer.
    In this respect our age is the age of enlightenment, the century of access
    to knowledge.
            This spirit of freedom is also spreading globally, even where it has to
    struggle with outward obstacles imposed by governments which misunderstand
    their own function. For such governments now witness examples of how
    freedom may exist without in the least jeopardizing public concord and the
    unity of the commonwealth. Citizens will of their own accord gradually work
    their way out of barbarism so long as artificial measures are not
    deliberately adopted to keep them in it.
            I have portrayed religious and ethical deliberation as the focal point of
    enlightenment. Our political leaders have no interest in assuming the role
    of guardians over their citizens in regard to the arts and sciences. But
    the attitude of heads of state who favor freedom in the arts and sciences
    extends even further, for they realize that there's no danger even to law
    and order if the rest of us are permitted to make public use of our own
    reason, even if this entails forthright criticism of current legislation.
            It boils down to this, then: Argue as much as you like on any topic, but
    obey the law! Considered in the widest sense, in human affairs nearly
    everything is paradoxical. A high degree of civil freedom seems
    advantageous to a people's intellectual freedom, yet it also sets up
    insuperable barriers to it. Conversely, a lesser degree of civil freedom
    gives intellectual freedom enough room to expand to its fullest extent.
    What is special and singular in human nature, our inclination and vocation
    to think freely, can develop inside these socially stabilizing constraints,
    and gradually changes the way we view the world and our capacity to act in
    it. Bit by bit, we become increasingly able to act freely. Eventually, even
    governments learn that they can profit by treating men and women-who are
    more than simple machines-in a manner appropriate to our dignity.



    This archive was generated by hypermail 2.1.5 : Tue Aug 19 2003 - 19:48:29 MDT